Repressive Tolerance Herbert Marcuse (1965).pdf

(130 KB) Pobierz
Repressive Tolerance
Herbert Marcuse
(1965)
This essay is dedicated to my students at Brandeis University
— H.M.
Footnotes and Endnotes added by Arun Chandra
This essay examines the idea of tolerance in our ad-
vanced industrial society. The conclusion reached is that
the realization of the objective of tolerance would call
for intolerance toward prevailing policies, attitudes, opin-
ions, and the extension of tolerance to policies, attitudes,
and opinions which are outlawed or suppressed. In other
words, today tolerance appears again as what it was in its
origins, at the beginning of the modem period — a parti-
san
1
goal, a subversive liberating notion and practice. Con-
versely, what is proclaimed and practiced as tolerance to-
day, is in many of its most effective manifestations serving
the cause of oppression.
The author is fully aware that, at present, no power, no
authority, no government exists which would translate lib-
erating tolerance into practice, but he believes that it is the
task and duty of the intellectual to recall and preserve his-
torical possibilities which seem to have become utopian
possibilities — that it is his task to break the concreteness
of oppression in order to open the mental space in which
this society can be recognized as what it is and does.
OLERANCE is an end in itself. The elimination of
violence, and the reduction of suppression to the ex-
tent required for protecting man and animals from cruelty
and aggression are preconditions for the creation of a hu-
mane society. Such a society does not yet exist; progress
toward it is perhaps more than before arrested by vio-
lence and suppression on a global scale. As deterrents
against nuclear war, as police action against subversion,
as technical aid in the fight against imperialism and com-
munism, as methods of pacification in neo-colonial mas-
sacres, violence and suppression are promulgated,
2
prac-
ticed, and defended by democratic and authoritarian gov-
ernments alike, and the people subjected to these gov-
ernments are educated to sustain such practices as neces-
T
sary for the preservation of the
status quo
3
. Tolerance is
extended to policies, conditions, and modes of behavior
which should not be tolerated because they are impeding,
if not destroying, the chances of creating an existence
without fear and misery.
This sort of tolerance strengthens the tyranny of the
majority against which authentic liberals protested. The
political locus
4
of tolerance has changed: while it is more
or less quietly and constitutionally withdrawn from the
opposition, it is made compulsory behavior with respect
to established policies. Tolerance is turned from an ac-
tive into a passive state, from practice to non-practice:
laissez-faire
5
the constituted authorities. It is the peo-
ple who tolerate the government, which in turn tolerates
opposition within the framework determined by the con-
stituted authorities.
Tolerance toward that which is radically evil now ap-
pears as good because it serves the cohesion of the whole
on the road to affluence or more affluence. The tol-
eration of the systematic moronization of children and
adults alike by publicity and propaganda, the release of
destructiveness in aggressive driving, the recruitment for
and training of special forces, the impotent and benevo-
lent tolerance toward outright deception in merchandis-
ing, waste, and planned obsolescence are not distortions
and aberrations: they are the essence of a system which
fosters tolerance as a means for perpetuating the strug-
gle for existence and suppressing the alternatives. The
authorities in education, morals, and psychology are vo-
ciferous
6
against the increase in juvenile delinquency;
they are less vociferous against the proud presentation,
prejudiced in favor of a particular cause.
promote or make widely known (an idea or cause).
3
status quo:
the existing state of affairs, esp. regarding social or political issues.
4
locus:
the effective or perceiveed location of something abstract.
5
laissez-faire:
a doctrine opposing governmental interference in economic affairs beyond the minimum necessary for the maintenance of peace
and property rights.
6
vociferous:
vehement or clamorous.
2
promulgate:
1
partisan:
H
ERBERT
M
ARCUSE
1
Repressive Tolerance
in word and deed and pictures, of ever more powerful
missiles, rockets, bombs — the mature delinquency of a
whole civilization.
According to a dialectical
7
proposition it is the whole
which determines the truth — not in the sense that the
whole is prior or superior to its parts, but in the sense
that its structure and function determine every particular
condition and relation. Thus, within a repressive society,
even progressive movements threaten to turn into their
opposite to the degree to which they accept the rules of
the game. To take a most controversial case: the exer-
cise of political rights (such as voting, letter-writing to
the press, to Senators, etc., protest-demonstrations with
a priori
8
renunciation of counter-violence) in a society
of total administration serves to strengthen this adminis-
tration by testifying to the existence of democratic lib-
erties which, in reality, have changed their content and
lost their effectiveness. In such a case, freedom (of opin-
ion, of assembly, of speech) becomes an instrument for
absolving
9
servitude. And yet (and only here the di-
alectical proposition shows its full intent) the existence
and practice of these liberties remain a precondition for
the restoration of their original oppositional function,
provided that the effort to transcend their (often self-
imposed) limitations is intensified. Generally, the func-
tion and value of tolerance depend on the equality preva-
lent in the society in which tolerance is practiced. Toler-
ance itself stands subject to overriding criteria: its range
and its limits cannot be defined in terms of the respective
society. In other words, tolerance is an end in itself only
when it is truly universal, practiced by the rulers as well
as by the ruled, by the lords as well as by the peasants,
by the sheriffs as well as by their victims. And such uni-
versal tolerance is possible only when no real or alleged
enemy requires in the national interest the education and
training of people in military violence and destruction.
As long as these conditions do not prevail, the condi-
tions of tolerance are “loaded”: they are determined and
defined by the institutionalized inequality (which is cer-
tainly compatible with constitutional equality),
i.e.,
by
the class structure of society. In such a society, tolerance
is
de facto
10
limited on the dual ground of legalized vio-
lence or suppression (police, armed forces, guards of all
sorts) and of the privileged position held by the predom-
inant interests and their “connections.”
7
dialectical:
8
a
These background limitations of tolerance are nor-
mally prior to the explicit and judicial limitations as de-
fined by the courts, custom, governments, etc. (for ex-
ample, “clear and present danger,” threat to national se-
curity, heresy). Within the framework of such a so-
cial structure, tolerance can be safety practiced and pro-
claimed. It is of two kinds: (1) the passive toleration
of entrenched and established attitudes and ideas even if
their damaging effect on man and nature is evident; and
(2) the active, official tolerance granted to the Right as
well as to the Left, to movements of aggression as well
as to movements of peace, to the party of hate as well
as to that of humanity. I call this non-partisan tolerance
“abstract” or “pure” inasmuch as it refrains from taking
sides — but in doing so it actually protects the already
established machinery of discrimination.
The tolerance which enlarged the range and content
of freedom was always partisan — intolerant toward the
protagonists
11
of the repressive
status quo.
The issue was
only the degree and extent of intolerance. In the firmly
established liberal society of England and the United
States, freedom of speech and assembly was granted
even to the radical enemies of society, provided they did
not make the transition from word to deed, from speech
to action.
Relying on the effective background limitations im-
posed by its class structure, the society seemed to prac-
tice general tolerance. But liberalist theory had already
placed an important condition on tolerance: it was “to
apply only to human beings in the maturity of their fac-
ulties.” John Stuart Mill
12
does not only speak of children
and minors; he elaborates:
“Liberty, as a principle, has no application to any state of
things anterior
13
to the time when mankind have become
capable of being improved by free and equal discussion.”
Anterior to that time, men may still be barbarians, and
“despotism
14
is a legitimate mode of government in deal-
ing with barbarians, provided the end be their improve-
ment, and the means justified by actually effecting that
end.”
Mill’s often-quoted words have a less familiar impli-
cation on which their meaning depends: the internal
connection between liberty and truth. There is a sense
in which truth is the end of liberty, and liberty must
be defined and confined by truth. Now in what sense
concerned with or acting through opposing forces.
priori:
formed or conceived beforehand.
9
absolve:
set or declare (someone) free from blame, guilt, or responsibility.
10
de facto:
in fact, whether by right or not.
11
protagonist:
an advocate or champion of a particular cause or idea.
12
John Stuart Mill (1806–1873): British philosopher and political economist, influential liberal thinker of the 19th century.
13
anterior:
coming before in time; earlier.
14
despotism:
the exercise of absolute power, esp. in a cruel and oppressive way.
H
ERBERT
M
ARCUSE
2
Repressive Tolerance
can liberty be for the sake of truth? Liberty is self-
determination, autonomy — this is almost a tautology,
15
but a tautology which results from a whole series of syn-
thetic judgments. It stipulates the ability to determine
one’s own life: to be able to determine what to do and
what not to do, what to suffer and what not. But the sub-
ject of this autonomy is never the contingent,
16
private
individual as that which he actually is or happens to be;
it is rather the individual as a human being who is capable
of being free with the others. And the problem of making
possible such a harmony between every individual liberty
and the other is not that of finding a compromise between
competitors, or between freedom and law, between gen-
eral and individual interest, common and private welfare
in an
established
society, but of
creating
the society in
which man is no longer enslaved by institutions which
vitiate
17
self-determination from the beginning. In other
words, freedom is still to be created even for the freest
of the existing societies. And the direction in which it
must be sought, and the institutional and cultural changes
which may help to attain the goal are, at least in devel-
oped civilization,
comprehensible,
that is to say, they can
be identified and projected, on the basis of experience,
by human reason.
In the interplay of theory and practice, true and false
solutions become distinguishable — never with the ev-
idence of necessity, never as the positive, only with the
certainty of a reasoned and reasonable chance, and with
the persuasive force of the negative. For the true positive
is the society of the future and therefore beyond defini-
tion and determination, while the existing positive is that
which must be surmounted.
18
But the experience and un-
derstanding of the existent society may well be capable
of identifying what is not conducive to a free and ratio-
nal society, what impedes and distorts the possibilities of
its creation. Freedom is liberation, a specific historical
process in theory and practice, and as such it has its right
and wrong, its truth and falsehood.
The uncertainty of chance in this distinction does
not cancel the historical objectivity, but it necessitates
freedom of thought and expression as preconditions of
finding the way to freedom — it necessitates
tolerance.
However, this tolerance cannot be indiscriminate and
equal with respect to the contents of expression, neither
in word nor in deed; it cannot protect false words and
15
tautology:
wrong deeds which demonstrate that they contradict and
counteract the possibilities of liberation. Such indiscrim-
inate tolerance is justified in harmless debates, in conver-
sation, in academic discussion; it is indispensable in the
scientific enterprise, in private religion. But society can-
not be indiscriminate where the pacification of existence,
where freedom and happiness themselves are at stake:
here, certain things cannot be said, certain ideas cannot
be expressed, certain policies cannot be proposed, certain
behavior cannot be permitted without making tolerance
an instrument for the continuation of servitude.
The danger of “destructive tolerance” (Baudelaire
19
),
of “benevolent neutrality” toward
art
has been recog-
nized: the market, which absorbs equally well (although
with often quite sudden fluctuations) art, anti-art, and
non-art, all possible conflicting styles, schools, forms,
provides a “complacent receptacle, a friendly abyss”
20
in
which the radical impact of art, the protest of art against
the established reality is swallowed up. However, cen-
sorship of art and literature is regressive under all cir-
cumstances. The authentic
œuvre
21
is not and cannot be
a prop of oppression, and pseudo-art (which can be such
a prop) is not art. Art stands against history, withstands
history which has been the history of oppression, for art
subjects reality to laws other than the established ones:
to the laws of the Form which creates a different reality
— negation of the established one even where art depicts
the established reality. But in its struggle with history,
art subjects itself to history: history enters the defini-
tion of art and enters into the distinction between art and
pseudo-art. Thus it happens that what was once art be-
comes pseudo-art. Previous forms, styles, and qualities,
previous modes of protest and refusal cannot be recap-
tured in or against a different society. There are cases
where an authentic
œuvre
carries a regressive political
message — Dostoevsky
22
is a case in point, But then, the
message is canceled by the
œuvre
itself: the regressive
political content is absorbed [aufgehoben] in the artistic
form: in the work as literature.
Tolerance of free speech is the way of improvement,
of progress in liberation,
not
because there is no objective
truth, and improvement must necessarily be a compro-
mise between a variety of opinions, but because there is
an objective truth which can be discovered, ascertained
only in learning and comprehending that which is and
a phrase or expression in which the same thing is said twice in different words.
subject to or at the mercy of accidents; liable to chance and change.
17
vitiate:
to make ineffective.
18
surmount:
overcome (a difficulty or obstacle).
19
Charles Baudelaire (1821–1867) one of the most influential French poets of the 19th century.
20
Edgar Wind,
Art and Anarchy
(New York: Knopf, 1964), p. 101
21
œuvre:
a work of art, music, or literature (French).
22
Fyodor Dostoevsky (1821–81) Russian novelist.
16
contingent:
H
ERBERT
M
ARCUSE
3
Repressive Tolerance
that which can be and ought to be done for the sake of
improving the lot of mankind. This common and histor-
ical “ought” is not immediately evident, at hand: it has
to be uncovered by “cutting through,” splitting, “break-
ing asunder” (dis-cutio) the given material — separat-
ing right and wrong, good and bad, correct and incorrect.
The subject whose “improvement” depends on a progres-
sive historical practice is each man as man, and this uni-
versality is reflected in that of the discussion, which
a
priori
does not exclude any group or individual. But even
the all-inclusive character of liberalist tolerance was, at
least in theory, based on the proposition that men were
(potential)
individuals
who could learn to hear and see
and feel by themselves, to develop their own thoughts, to
grasp their true interests and rights and capabilities, also
against established authority and opinion. This was the
rationale of free speech and assembly. Universal tolera-
tion becomes questionable when its rationale no longer
prevails, when tolerance is administered to manipulated
and indoctrinated individuals who parrot, as their own,
the opinion of their masters, for whom heteronomy
23
has
become autonomy.
24
The
telos
25
of tolerance is truth. It is clear from the
historical record that the authentic spokesmen of toler-
ance had more and other truth in mind than that of propo-
sitional logic and academic theory. John Stuart Mill
speaks of the truth which is persecuted in history and
which does
not
triumph over persecution by virtue of its
“inherent power,” which in fact has no inherent power
“against the dungeon and the stake.” And he enumerates
the “truths” which were cruelly and successfully liqui-
dated in the dungeons and at the stake: that of Arnold of
Brescia, of Fra Dolcino, of Savonarola, of the Albigen-
sians, Waldensians, Lollards, and Hussites.
26
Tolerance
is first and foremost for the sake of the heretics — the his-
torical road toward
humanitas
27
appears as heresy: target
of persecution by the powers that be. Heresy by itself,
however, is no token of truth.
The criterion of progress in freedom according to
which Mill judges these movements is the Reformation.
The evaluation is
ex post,
28
and his list includes opposites
(Savonarola too would have burned Fra Dolcino). Even
the
ex post
evaluation is contestable as to its truth: history
corrects the judgment — too late. The correction does
23
heteronomy:
24
autonomy:
not help the victims and does not absolve their execution-
ers. However, the lesson is clear: intolerance has delayed
progress and has prolonged the slaughter and torture of
innocents for hundreds of years. Does this clinch the case
for indiscriminate, “pure” tolerance? Are there historical
conditions in which such toleration impedes liberation
and multiplies the victims who are sacrificed to the
status
quo?
Can the indiscriminate guaranty of political rights
and liberties be repressive? Can such tolerance serve to
contain qualitative social change?
I shall discuss this question only with reference to po-
litical movements, attitudes, schools of thought, philoso-
phies which are “political” in the widest sense — affect-
ing the society as a whole, demonstrably transcending
the sphere of privacy. Moreover, I propose a shift in the
focus of the discussion: it will be concerned not only, and
not primarily, with tolerance toward radical extremes,
minorities, subversives, etc., but rather with tolerance to-
ward majorities, toward official and public opinion, to-
ward the established protectors of freedom. In this case,
the discussion can have as a frame of reference only a
democratic society, in which the people, as individuals
and as members of political and other organizations, par-
ticipate in the making, sustaining, and changing policies.
In an authoritarian system, the people do not tolerate —
they suffer established policies.
Under a system of constitutionally guaranteed and
(generally and without too many and too glaring excep-
tions) practiced civil rights and liberties, opposition and
dissent are tolerated unless they issue in violence and/or
in exhortation to and organization of violent subversion.
The underlying assumption is that the established society
is free, and that any improvement, even a change in the
social structure and social values, would come about in
the normal course of events, prepared, defined, and tested
in free and equal discussion, on the open marketplace of
ideas and goods.
29
Now in recalling John Stuart Mill’s passage, I drew
attention to the premise hidden in this assumption: free
and equal discussion can fulfill the function attributed to
it only if it is
rational
— expression and development of
independent thinking, free from indoctrination, manipu-
lation, extraneous authority. The notion of pluralism and
countervailing powers is no substitute for this require-
subjection to something else; especially: a lack of moral freedom or self-determination.
self-directing freedom and especially moral independence.
25
telos:
an ultimate end.
26
See notes at end for these references.
27
humanitas:
humanity
28
ex post:
based on actual results rather than on forecasts.
29
I wish to reiterate for the following discussion that,
de facto,
tolerance is not indiscriminate and “pure” even in the most democratic society.
The “background limitations” stated earlier in this article (on page 2) restrict tolerance before it begins to operate. The antagonistic structure of
society rigs the rules of the game. Those who stand against the established system are
a priori
at a disadvantage, which is not removed by the
toleration of their ideas, speeches, and newspapers. [Note by Marcuse.]
H
ERBERT
M
ARCUSE
4
Repressive Tolerance
ment. One might in theory construct a state in which a
multitude of different pressures, interests, and authorities
balance each other out and result in a truly general and
rational interest. However, such a construct badly fits a
society in which powers are and remain unequal and even
increase their unequal weight when they run their own
course. It fits even worse when the variety of pressures
unifies and coagulates into an overwhelming whole, inte-
grating the particular countervailing powers by virtue of
an increasing standard of living and an increasing con-
centration of power. Then, the laborer, whose real in-
terest conflicts with that of management, the common
consumer whose real interest conflicts with that of the
producer, the intellectual whose vocation conflicts with
that of his employer find themselves submitting to a sys-
tem against which they are powerless and appear unrea-
sonable. The ideas of the available alternatives evapo-
rates into an utterly utopian dimension in which it is at
home, for a free society is indeed unrealistically and un-
definably different from the existing ones. Under these
circumstances, whatever improvement may occur “in the
normal course of events” and without subversion is likely
to be improvement in the direction determined by the
particular interests which control the whole.
By the same token, those minorities which strive for a
change of the whole itself will, under optimal conditions
which rarely prevail, be left free to deliberate and dis-
cuss, to speak and to assemble — and will be left harm-
less and helpless in the face of the overwhelming ma-
jority, which militates against qualitative social change.
This majority is firmly grounded in the increasing satis-
faction of needs, and technological and mental coordina-
tion, which testify to the general helplessness of radical
groups in a well-functioning social system.
Within the affluent democracy, the affluent discus-
sion prevails, and within the established framework, it
is tolerant to a large extent. All points of view can be
heard: the Communist and the Fascist, the Left and the
Right, the white and the Negro, the crusaders for arma-
ment and for disarmament. Moreover, in endlessly drag-
ging debates over the media, the stupid opinion is treated
with the same respect as the intelligent one, the misin-
formed may talk as long as the informed, and propaganda
rides along with education, truth with falsehood. This
pure toleration of sense and nonsense is justified by the
democratic argument that nobody, neither group nor indi-
vidual, is in possession of the truth and capable of defin-
ing what is right and wrong, good and bad. Therefore,
all contesting opinions must be submitted to “the peo-
ple” for its deliberation and choice. But I have already
suggested that the democratic argument implies a neces-
sary condition, namely, that the people must be capable
H
ERBERT
M
ARCUSE
5
of deliberating and choosing on the basis of knowledge,
that they must have access to authentic information, and
that, on this basis, their evaluation must be the result of
autonomous thought.
In the Contemporary period, the democratic argu-
ment for abstract tolerance tends to be invalidated by the
invalidation of the democratic process itself. The liberat-
ing force of democracy was the chance it gave to effec-
tive dissent, on the individual as well as social scale, its
openness to qualitatively different forms of government,
of culture, education, work — of the human existence in
general. The toleration of free discussion and the equal
right of opposites was to define and clarify the different
forms of dissent: their direction, content, prospect. But
with the concentration of economic and political power
and the integration of opposites in a society which uses
technology as an instrument of domination, effective dis-
sent is blocked where it could freely emerge: in the for-
mation of opinion, in information and communication,
in speech and assembly. Under the rule of monopolistic
media — themselves the mere instruments of economic
and political power — a mentality is created for which
right and wrong, true and false are predefined wherever
they affect the vital interests of the society. This is, prior
to all expression and communication, a matter of seman-
tics: the blocking of effective dissent, of the recognition
of that which is not of the Establishment which begins
in the language that is publicized and administered. The
meaning of words is rigidly stabilized. Rational persua-
sion, persuasion to the opposite is all but precluded. The
avenues of entrance are closed to the meaning of words
and ideas other than the established one — established by
the publicity of the powers that be, and verified in their
practices. Other words can be spoken and heard, other
ideas can be expressed, but, at the massive scale of the
conservative majority (outside such enclaves as the in-
telligentsia), they are immediately “evaluated” (i.e., au-
tomatically understood) in terms of the public language
— a language which determines
a priori
the direction in
which the thought process moves. Thus the process of
reflection ends where it started: in the given conditions
and relations. Self-validating, the argument of the dis-
cussion repels the contradiction because the antithesis is
redefined in terms of the thesis. For example, thesis: we
work for peace; antithesis: we prepare for war (or even:
we wage war); unification of opposites: preparing for
war
is
working for peace. Peace is redefined as necessar-
ily, in the prevailing situation, including preparation for
war (or even war) and in this Orwellian form, the mean-
ing of the word “peace” is stabilized. Thus, the basic
vocabulary of the Orwellian language operates as
a pri-
ori
categories of understanding: preforming all content.
Repressive Tolerance
Zgłoś jeśli naruszono regulamin